Help


[permalink] [id link]
+
Page "Euclidean geometry" ¶ 102
from Wikipedia
Edit
Promote Demote Fragment Fix

Some Related Sentences

Hilbert's and axioms
: Foundations of Geometry ) published by Hilbert in 1899 proposes a formal set, the Hilbert's axioms, substituting the traditional axioms of Euclid.
Some of the axioms coincide, while some of the axioms in Moore's system are theorems in Hilbert's and vice-versa.
* Hilbert's axioms
In logic, the second problem on David Hilbert's list of open problems presented in 1900 was to prove that the axioms of arithmetic are consistent.
* Tarski's axioms: Alfred Tarski ( 1902 – 1983 ) and his students defined elementary Euclidean geometry as the geometry that can be expressed in first-order logic and does not depend on set theory for its logical basis, in contrast to Hilbert's axioms, which involve point sets.
The process of abstract axiomatization as exemplified by Hilbert's axioms reduces geometry to theorem proving or predicate logic.
* Hilbert's axioms
He started with the " betweenness " of Hilbert's axioms to characterize space without coordinatizing it, and then added extra relations between points to do the work formerly done by vector fields.
Hilbert's system consisting of 20 axioms < ref > a 21 < sup > st </ sup > axiom appeared in the French translation of Hilbert's Grundlagen der Geometrie according to most closely follows the approach of Euclid and provides the justification for all of Euclid's proofs.
The two results are widely, but not universally, interpreted as showing that Hilbert's program to find a complete and consistent set of axioms for all mathematics is impossible, giving a negative answer to Hilbert's second problem.
These do not provide a resolution to Hilbert's second question, however, because someone who doubts the consistency of Peano arithmetic is unlikely to accept the axioms of set theory ( which is much stronger ) to prove its consistency.
One of the main goals of Hilbert's program was a finitistic proof of the consistency of the axioms of arithmetic: that is his second problem.
This dealt a final blow to the heart of Hilbert's program, the hope that consistency could be established by finitistic means ( it was never made clear exactly what axioms were the " finitistic " ones, but whatever axiomatic system was being referred to, it was a ' weaker ' system than the system whose consistency it was supposed to prove ).
The notion arose from the theory of magnitudes of Ancient Greece ; it still plays an important role in modern mathematics such as David Hilbert's axioms for geometry, and the theories of ordered groups, ordered fields, and local fields.

Hilbert's and had
In announcing the prize, CMI drew a parallel to Hilbert's problems, which were proposed in 1900, and had a substantial impact on 20th century mathematics.
Those forced out included Hermann Weyl ( who had taken Hilbert's chair when he retired in 1930 ), Emmy Noether and Edmund Landau.
In an account that had become standard by the mid-century, Hilbert's problem set was also a kind of manifesto, that opened the way for the development of the formalist school, one of three major schools of mathematics of the 20th century.
Hilbert's work had started logic on this course of clarification ; the need to understand Gödel's work then led to the development of recursion theory and then mathematical logic as an autonomous discipline in the 1930s.
By early summer 1915, Hilbert's interest in physics had focused on general relativity, and he invited Einstein to Göttingen to deliver a week of lectures on the subject.
When his colleague Richard Courant wrote the now classic Methods of Mathematical Physics including some of Hilbert's ideas, he added Hilbert's name as author even though Hilbert had not directly contributed to the writing.
Since 1900, other mathematicians and mathematical organizations have announced problem lists, but, with few exceptions, these collections have not had nearly as much influence nor generated as much work as Hilbert's problems.
There was some irony that in the pushing through of David Hilbert's long-range programme a natural home for intuitionistic logic's central ideas was found: Hilbert had detested the school of L. E. J. Brouwer.
This became known as the Kronecker Jugendtraum ; and was certainly what had prompted Hilbert's remark above, since it makes explicit class field theory in the way the roots of unity do for abelian extensions of the rational number field, via Shimura's reciprocity law.
The ideal theory in question had been based on elimination theory, but in line with David Hilbert's taste moved away from algorithmic methods.
They were able to show the solutions had first derivatives that were Hölder continuous, which by previous results implied that the solutions are analytic whenever the differential equation has analytic coefficients, thus completing the solution of Hilbert's nineteenth problem.

Hilbert's and goal
The 6th problem concerns the axiomatization of physics, a goal that twentieth century developments of physics ( including its recognition as a discipline independent from mathematics ) seem to render both more remote and less important than in Hilbert's time.
The main goal of Hilbert's program was to provide secure foundations for all mathematics.

Hilbert's and identifying
Church and Turing independently demonstrated that Hilbert's Entscheidungsproblem ( decision problem ) was unsolvable, thus identifying the computational core of the incompleteness theorem.
Bieberbach wrote a habilitation thesis in 1911 about groups of Euclidean motions – identifying conditions under which the group must have a translational subgroup whose vectors span the Euclidean space – that helped solve Hilbert's 18th problem.

Hilbert's and simple
simple: Hilbert's paradox of the Grand Hotel

Hilbert's and complete
Hilbert's goals of creating a system of mathematics that is both complete and consistent were dealt a fatal blow by the second of Gödel's incompleteness theorems, which states that sufficiently expressive consistent axiom systems can never prove their own consistency.
* Hilbert's theorem ( 1901 ) states that there exists no complete analytic ( class C < sup > ω </ sup >) regular surface in R < sup > 3 </ sup > of constant negative Gaussian curvature.
The non-abelian generalization, also connected with Hilbert's twelfth problem, is one of the long-standing challenges in number theory and is far from being complete.

Hilbert's and set
As a result, he demonstrated Hilbert's basis theorem: showing the existence of a finite set of generators, for the invariants of quantics in any number of variables, but in an abstract form.
Because there exists a recursively enumerable set that is not computable, the unsolvability of Hilbert's tenth problem is an immediate consequence.
0 for all f in I. Hilbert's Nullstellensatz states that if p is some polynomial in kX < sub > n </ sub > which vanishes on the algebraic set V ( I ), i. e. p ( x ) = 0 for all x in V ( I ), then there exists a natural number r such that p < sup > r </ sup > is in I.
The end of the millennium, being also the centennial of Hilbert's announcement of his problems, was a natural occasion to propose " a new set of Hilbert problems.
Many axiomatic systems were developed in the nineteenth century, including non-Euclidean geometry, the foundations of real analysis, Cantor's set theory and Frege's work on foundations, and Hilbert's ' new ' use of axiomatic method as a research tool.
To see the connection with the classical picture, note that for any set S of polynomials ( over an algebraically closed field ), it follows from Hilbert's Nullstellensatz that the points of V ( S ) ( in the old sense ) are exactly the tuples ( a < sub > 1 </ sub >, ..., a < sub > n </ sub >) such that ( x < sub > 1 </ sub >-a < sub > 1 </ sub >, ..., x < sub > n </ sub >-a < sub > n </ sub >) contains S ; moreover, these are maximal ideals and by the " weak " Nullstellensatz, an ideal of any affine coordinate ring is maximal if and only if it is of this form.
* it motivated the currently prevalent philosophical position that all of mathematics should be derivable from logic and set theory, ultimately leading to Hilbert's program, Gödel's theorems and non-standard analysis.
The Diophantine characterizations of a recursively enumerable set, while not as straightforward or intuitive as the first definitions, were found by Yuri Matiyasevich as part of the negative solution to Hilbert's Tenth Problem.
* David Hilbert publishes Grundlagen der Geometrie, proposing a formal set, Hilbert's axioms, to replace Euclid's elements.
This coincides with the ordinal successor operation for finite cardinals, but in the infinite case they diverge because every infinite ordinal and its successor have the same cardinality ( a bijection can be set up between the two by simply sending the last element of the successor to 0, 0 to 1, etc., and fixing ω and all the elements above ; in the style of Hilbert's Hotel Infinity ).
Hilbert's axioms are a set of 20 ( originally 21 ) assumptions proposed by David Hilbert in 1899 in his book Grundlagen der Geometrie ( tr.
* Hilbert's paradox of the Grand Hotel, a mathematical paradox related to set theory and countable infinities
The work of Lubotzky and Mann, combined with Michel Lazard's solution to Hilbert's fifth problem over the p-adic numbers, shows that a pro-p group is p-adic analytic if and only if it has finite rank, i. e. there exists a positive integer such that any closed subgroup has a topological generating set with no more than elements.
Hilbert's twenty-third problem is the last of Hilbert problems set out in a celebrated list compiled in 1900 by David Hilbert.
Hilbert's thirteenth problem is one of the 23 Hilbert problems set out in a celebrated list compiled in 1900 by David Hilbert.
Hilbert's fifteenth problem is one of the 23 Hilbert problems set out in a celebrated list compiled in 1900 by David Hilbert.
Hilbert's seventeenth problem is one of the 23 Hilbert problems set out in a celebrated list compiled in 1900 by David Hilbert.

0.694 seconds.