Help


[permalink] [id link]
+
Page "Turing completeness" ¶ 13
from Wikipedia
Edit
Promote Demote Fragment Fix

Some Related Sentences

Gödel's and completeness
** Gödel's completeness theorem for first-order logic: every consistent set of first-order sentences has a completion.
Gödel's completeness theorem establishes the completeness of a certain commonly used type of deductive system.
Note that " completeness " has a different meaning here than it does in the context of Gödel's first incompleteness theorem, which states that no recursive, consistent set of non-logical axioms of the Theory of Arithmetic is complete, in the sense that there will always exist an arithmetic statement such that neither nor can be proved from the given set of axioms.
For a first order predicate calculus, with no (" proper ") axioms, Gödel's completeness theorem states that the theorems ( provable statements ) are exactly the logically valid well-formed formulas, so identifying valid formulas is recursively enumerable: given unbounded resources, any valid formula can eventually be proven.
Gödel's completeness theorem is a fundamental theorem in mathematical logic that establishes a correspondence between semantic truth and syntactic provability in first-order logic.
Gödel's completeness theorem says that a deductive system of first-order predicate calculus is " complete " in the sense that no additional inference rules are required to prove all the logically valid formulas.
In modern logic texts, Gödel's completeness theorem is usually proved with Henkin's proof, rather than with Gödel's original proof.
* Original proof of Gödel's completeness theorem
The proof of Gödel's completeness theorem given by Kurt Gödel in his doctoral dissertation of 1929 ( and a rewritten version of the dissertation, published as an article in 1930 ) is not easy to read today ; it uses concepts and formalism that are outdated and terminology that is often obscure.
Attending a lecture by David Hilbert in Bologna on completeness and consistency of mathematical systems may have set Gödel's life course.
In it, he established the completeness of the first-order predicate calculus ( Gödel's completeness theorem ).
Examples of early theorems from classical model theory include Gödel's completeness theorem, the upward and downward Löwenheim – Skolem theorems, Vaught's two-cardinal theorem, Scott's isomorphism theorem, the omitting types theorem, and the Ryll-Nardzewski theorem.
In 1930, Gödel's completeness theorem showed that propositional logic itself was complete in a much weaker sense — that is, any sentence that is unprovable from a given set of axioms must actually be false in some model of the axioms.
# REDIRECT Gödel's completeness theorem
One can prove the compactness theorem using Gödel's completeness theorem, which establishes that a set of sentences is satisfiable if and only if no contradiction can be proven from it.
In fact, the compactness theorem is equivalent to Gödel's completeness theorem, and both are equivalent to the Boolean prime ideal theorem, a weak form of the axiom of choice.
Isabelle has been used to formalize numerous theorems from mathematics and computer science, like Gödel's completeness theorem, Gödel's theorem about the consistency of the axiom of choice, the prime number theorem, correctness of security protocols, and properties of programming language semantics.
Kurt Gödel's seminal work on proof theory first advanced, then refuted this program: his completeness theorem initially seemed to bode well for Hilbert's aim of reducing all mathematics to a finitist formal system ; then his incompleteness theorems showed that this is unattainable.
* Gödel's completeness theorem, 1930
Some examples are the Hahn – Banach theorem, König's lemma, Brouwer fixed point theorem, Gödel's completeness theorem and Jordan curve theorem.

Gödel's and theorem
The notion of the Kolmogorov complexity can be used to state and prove impossibility results akin to Gödel's incompleteness theorem and Turing's halting problem.
In mathematics, a Gödel code was the basis for the proof of Gödel's incompleteness theorem.
This incompleteness result is similar to Gödel's incompleteness theorem in that it shows that no consistent formal theory for arithmetic can be complete.
Gödel's second incompleteness theorem, proved in 1931, showed that this was not possible – at least not within arithmetic itself.
( This doesn't violate Gödel's theorem, because Euclidean geometry cannot describe a sufficient amount of arithmetic for the theorem to apply.
The work of both authors was heavily influenced by Kurt Gödel's earlier work on his incompleteness theorem, especially by the method of assigning numbers ( a Gödel numbering ) to logical formulas in order to reduce logic to arithmetic.
Gödel's incompleteness theorem, another celebrated result, shows that there are inherent limitations in what can be achieved with formal proofs in mathematics.
Gödel's original proof of the theorem proceeded by reducing the problem to a special case for formulas in a certain syntactic form, and then handling this form with an ad hoc argument.
Gödel's incompleteness theorem marks not only a milestone in recursion theory and proof theory, but has also led to Löb's theorem in modal logic.

Gödel's and 1930
* Proof of the semantic completeness of first order predicate logic ( Gödel's completeness theorem 1930 )

Gödel's and contains
Or if there is a measurable cardinal, then iterating the definable powerset operation rather than the full one yields Gödel's constructible universe, L, which does not satisfy the statement " there is a measurable cardinal " ( even though it contains the measurable cardinal as an ordinal ).

Gödel's and definition
Since most physicists would consider the statement of the underlying rules to suffice as the definition of a " theory of everything ", most physicists argue that Gödel's Theorem does not mean that a ToE cannot exist.

Gödel's and computer
Gödel's theorem shows that, in theories that include a small portion of number theory, a complete and consistent finite list of axioms can never be created, nor even an infinite list that can be enumerated by a computer program.
# For any logical system L a sufficiently skilled mathematical logician ( equipped with a sufficiently powerful computer if necessary ) can construct some statements T ( L ) which are true but unprovable in L. ( This follows from Gödel's first theorem.
# Mathematical Objections: This objection uses mathematical theorems, such as Gödel's incompleteness theorem, to show that there are limits to what questions a computer system based on logic can answer.
The Penrose / Lucas argument about the implications of Gödel's incompleteness theorem for computational theories of human intelligence has been widely criticized by mathematicians, computer scientists and philosophers, and the consensus among experts in these fields seems to be that the argument fails, though different authors may choose different aspects of the argument to attack.

Gödel's and because
This will not result in a complete theory, because Gödel's theorem will also apply to T ’, and thus T ’ cannot be complete.
Detlefsen ( 1990: p. 65 ) argues that Gödel's theorem does not prevent a consistency proof because its hypotheses might not apply to all the systems in which a consistency proof could be carried out.
It's gone topsy-turvy, not because of any philosophical argument, not because of Gödel's results or Turing's results or my own incompleteness results.
( Strictly speaking this result only appeared a few years after Gödel's theorem, because at the time the notion of an algorithm had not been precisely defined.
This does not contradict Gödel's first incompleteness theorem, because Tarski's theory lacks the expressive power needed to interpret Robinson arithmetic.
Q fascinates because it is a finitely axiomatized first-order theory that is considerably weaker than Peano arithmetic ( PA ), and whose axioms contain only one existential quantifier, yet like PA is incomplete and incompletable in the sense of Gödel's Incompleteness Theorems, and essentially undecidable.
If the system is suitably complex, like first-order arithmetic, then the set T of Gödel numbers of true sentences in the system will be a productive set, which means that whenever W is a recursively enumerable set of true sentences, there is at least one true sentence that is not in W. This can be used to give a rigorous proof of Gödel's first incompleteness theorem, because no recursively enumerable set is productive.

0.273 seconds.