Help


[permalink] [id link]
+
Page "Philosophical Investigations" ¶ 46
from Wikipedia
Edit
Promote Demote Fragment Fix

Some Related Sentences

Tractatus and Bertrand
Both English translations of Tractatus include an introduction by Bertrand Russell.

Tractatus and Russell
After the First World War, Russell met with Wittgenstein again and helped him publish the Tractatus Logico Philosophicus, Wittgenstein's own version of Logical Atomism.
Nevertheless, the Tractatus differed so fundamentally from the philosophy of Russell that Wittgenstein always believed that Russell misunderstood the work.
: Russell, Introduction to Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, s: Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus / Introduction
Later when Russell went to China he left her with the task of arranging the publication of Wittgenstein ’ s Tractatus in England.

Tractatus and saw
In his extensive work Tractatus de legibus ac deo legislatore ( reprinted, London, 1679 ) he is to some extent the precursor of Grotius and Samuel Pufendorf, in making an important distinction between natural law and international law, which he saw as based on custom.

Tractatus and though
Traces of this insistence are to be met with in the Tractatus ad Theopompum, concerning the pasibility and impassibility of God ; this work seems to belong to Gregory, though in its general arrangement it reminds us of Methodius.
It also engaged with the thought of Baruch Spinoza, in Tractatus Theologico-Politicus, though he was named only as a " late author mightily in vogue ".

Tractatus and should
Indeed, Wittgenstein wrote in Tractatus Logico Philosophicus that some of the propositions contained in his own book should be regarded as nonsense.

Tractatus and be
The confusion that the Tractatus seeks to dispel is not a confused theory, such that a correct theory would be a proper way to clear the confusion, rather the need of any such theory is confused.
In the Tractatus coislinianus ( which may or may not be by Aristotle ), comedy is defined as involving three types of characters: the buffoon ( bômolochus ), the ironist ( eirôn ) and the imposter or boaster ( alazôn ).
Since the killer comes to see his whole act through the lens of the real Wittgenstein's philosophy ( including his mid-career reversal following Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus ), it's hoped that he will be amenable to philosophical persuasion.
However, this critique of metaphysics, carried on by the first Wittgenstein, in his 1921 Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, for example, has been in return criticized by philosophers, such as Heidegger in his 1927 Being and Time, as a form of positivism or, worse, scientism, which is accused of having decided to abandon the most important questions about humanity and the Being, under the pretext that no definitive answer can be brought to them.
Wittgenstein's view in the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus more or less agreed with Russell's that language ought to be reformulated so as to be unambiguous, so as to accurately represent the world, so that we could better deal with the questions of philosophy.
He regarded Wittgenstein as a philosopher with a genius for stating philosophical insights in striking and memorable language, but believed that Wittgenstein ( or at least, the Wittgenstein of the Tractatus ) made claims which could only be supported by recourse to metaphysics.
In the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus of Ludwig Wittgenstein, Proposition 6. 5 seeks to ground his philosophy of action ( Proposition 7: " Whereof one cannot speak, thereof one must be silent ").
It was this event which made him realize that the subject of this process could be described by pictures as well as in words -- the genesis of his picture theory of language ( Tractatus 2 .*).
Statement 6. 41 appears to be an appeal ; the word must shows up in striking contrast to the rest of Tractatus, which consist of declarative statements.

Tractatus and Wittgenstein
For example, Wittgenstein wrote in Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus: " The subject doesn't belong to the world, but it is a limit of the world " ( proposition 5. 632 ).
The later Wittgenstein rejected many of the conclusions of the Tractatus, arguing that the meaning of words is constituted by the function they perform within any given language-game.
Compare, for example, Proposition 4. 024 of the Tractatus, where Wittgenstein asserts that we understand a proposition when we know what happens if it is true, with Schlick's assertion that " To state the circumstances under which a proposition is true is the same as stating its meaning.
* Wittgenstein L., Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, trans.
According to the standard reading, in the Philosophical Investigations Wittgenstein repudiates many of his own earlier views, expressed in the Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus.
.. Ironically, this change came about as the result of criticism from Wittgenstein in his 1919 Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus.
:" There is another course, recommended by Wittgenstein † († Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, * 5. 54ff ) for philosophical reasons.
The Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus ( Latin for " Logical-Philosophical Treatise ") is the only book-length philosophical work published by the Austrian philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein in his lifetime.
Wittgenstein wrote the notes for Tractatus while he was a soldier during World War I and completed it when a prisoner of war at Como and later Cassino in August 1918.
Moreover, there has been extensive commentary on the relationship between the respective treatises of Wittgenstein ( Tractatus ) and Aquinas ( Summa Theologica ).
Although Wittgenstein did not use the term himself, his metaphysical view throughout the Tractatus is commonly referred to as logical atomism.
Wittgenstein concluded that with the Tractatus he had resolved all philosophical problems.
Schlick eventually convinced Wittgenstein to meet with members of the circle to discuss the Tractatus when he returned to Vienna ( he was then working as an architect ).
The main contention of such readings is that Wittgenstein in the Tractatus does not provide a theoretical account of language that relegates ethics and philosophy to a mystical realm of the unsayable.
The 32-minute production, named Wittgenstein Tractatus, features citations from the Tractatus and other works by Wittgenstein.
" The world is everything that is the case ," wrote Ludwig Wittgenstein in his influential Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, first published in 1922.
But in his later years, Wittgenstein wrote works which are often interpreted as conflicting with his positions in the Tractatus, and indeed the later Wittgenstein is mainly seen as the leading critic of the early Wittgenstein.
* Ludwig WittgensteinTractatus Logico-Philosophicus
Eventually Wittgenstein agreed to meet with Schlick and other Circle members to discuss the Tractatus and other ideas but he later found it necessary to restrict the visitors to sympathetic interlocutors.

Tractatus and took
Members of the Vienna Circle had a common attitude towards philosophy, consisting of an applied logical positivism drawn from Ludwig Wittgenstein, whose Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus formed the basis for the group's philosophy ( although Wittgenstein himself insisted that logical positivism was a gross misreading of his thinking, and took to reading poetry during meetings of the Vienna Circle ).
Ludwig Wittgenstein took several of his ideas from Mauthner, and acknowledges him in his Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus ( 1922 ).

Tractatus and ),
* Set Theory, Skolem's Paradox and the Tractatus, A. W. Moore, Analysis 45, # 1 ( January 1985 ), pp. 13 – 20.
The Tractatus caught the attention of the philosophers of the Vienna Circle ( 1921 – 1933 ), especially Rudolf Carnap and Moritz Schlick.
The Parisian scholastic Jean de Jandun praised the building as one of Paris's most beautiful structures in his " Tractatus de laudibus Parisius " ( 1323 ), citing " that most beautiful of chapels, the chapel of the king, most decently situated within the walls of the king's house, enjoys a complete and indissoluble structure of the most solid stone.
The later years of his life were spent in comparative quiet, devoted in part to the preparation of his expositions of the Psalms ( Tractatus super Psalmos ), for which he was largely indebted to Origen ; of his Commentarius in Evangelium Matthaei, an allegorical exegesis of the first Gospel ; and of his no longer extant translation of Origen's commentary on Job.
* Tractatus de Geomantia, & c. ( four books ), included in Fasciculus Geomanticus, & c., Verona, 1687.
In Tractatus de proportionibus ( 1328 ), Bradwardine extended the theory of proportions of Eudoxus of Cnidus to anticipate the concept of exponential growth, later developed by the Bernoulli and Euler, with compound interest as a special case.
* De continuo ( On the Continuum ), edited by John Emery Murdoch in ' Geometry and the Continuum in the Fourteenth Century: A Philosophical Analysis of Thomas Bradwardine's Tractatus de continuo ', Ph. D. thesis, University of Wisconsin, 1957.
Charles Moore Watson ( 1844 – 1916 ) proposes an alternate etymology: The Assize of Weights and Measures ( also known as Tractatus de Ponderibus et Mensuris ), one of the statutes of uncertain date from the reign of either Henry III or Edward I, thus before 1307, specifies " troni ponderacionem "— which the Public Record Commissioners translates as " troy weight ".
A central work for the newly founded discussion group was the Logisch-Philosophische Abhandlung ( Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus ), published by Ludwig Wittgenstein in 1921 ( in 1922 in German-English version ).
* Tractatus Eboracenses ( Tractates of York ), dealing with the relationship between kings and the Catholic Church, c. 1100
* Tractatus of Glanvill, the Tractatus de legibus et consuetudinibus regni Angliae ( Treatise on the laws and customs of the Kingdom of England ), the book of authority on English common law, written ca.
* Tractatus de Intellectus Emendatione ( On The Improvement Of The Understanding ), an unfinished work by Baruch Spinoza
* Tractatus de Purgatorio Sancti Patricii ( Treatise on Saint Patrick's Purgatory ), a Latin text of c. 1180-84
* Tractatus de superstitionibus ( disambiguation ), a title shared by two medieval tractates on superstition
* Wittgenstein Tractatus ( film ), a film by Peter Forgacs
According to Luca Gaurico's Tractatus astrologicus ( 1552 ), Francesco studied under Giovanni Angelo Testagrossa, but today this is considered somewhat unlikely.
He also wrote the Tractatus consolatorius de morte amici ( Consolation upon the death of a friend ), addressed to Louis upon the death of his son Louis in 1260.
Among his other publications were Seawater made Fresh ( 1684 ), the Nature and Use of the Salt contained in Epsom and such other Waters ( 1697 ), which was a rendering of his Tractatus de salis ( 1693 ), and Cosmologia Sacra ( 1701 ).

0.462 seconds.