Help


[permalink] [id link]
+
Page "Buckingham π theorem" ¶ 0
from Wikipedia
Edit
Promote Demote Fragment Fix

Some Related Sentences

theorem and loosely
Roughly speaking, the theorem states that although there are many series of results that may be produced by a random process, the one actually produced is most probably from a loosely defined set of outcomes that all have approximately the same chance of being the one actually realized.
In mathematics, Parseval's theorem usually refers to the result that the Fourier transform is unitary ; loosely, that the sum ( or integral ) of the square of a function is equal to the sum ( or integral ) of the square of its transform.
We can loosely interpret the theorem as being a generalization of the suspension isomorphism on ( co ) homology, because the Thom space of a trivial bundle on B of rank k is isomorphic to the kth suspension of B +, B with a disjoint point added.

theorem and states
** The Vitali theorem on the existence of non-measurable sets which states that there is a subset of the real numbers that is not Lebesgue measurable.
Note that " completeness " has a different meaning here than it does in the context of Gödel's first incompleteness theorem, which states that no recursive, consistent set of non-logical axioms of the Theory of Arithmetic is complete, in the sense that there will always exist an arithmetic statement such that neither nor can be proved from the given set of axioms.
has no zero in F. By contrast, the fundamental theorem of algebra states that the field of complex numbers is algebraically closed.
For example, the prime number theorem states that the number of prime numbers less than or equal to N is asymptotically equal to N / ln N. Therefore the proportion of prime integers is roughly 1 / ln N, which tends to 0.
For a first order predicate calculus, with no (" proper ") axioms, Gödel's completeness theorem states that the theorems ( provable statements ) are exactly the logically valid well-formed formulas, so identifying valid formulas is recursively enumerable: given unbounded resources, any valid formula can eventually be proven.
* The fundamental theorem of algebra states that the algebraic closure of the field of real numbers is the field of complex numbers.
Artin's theorem states that in an alternative algebra the subalgebra generated by any two elements is associative.
A generalization of Artin's theorem states that whenever three elements in an alternative algebra associate ( i. e. ) the subalgebra generated by those elements is associative.
The fundamental theorem of arithmetic states that any positive integer n can be represented uniquely as a product of powers of primes: where p < sub > 1 </ sub > < p < sub > 2 </ sub > < ... < p < sub > k </ sub > are primes and the a < sub > j </ sub > are positive integers.
In mathematics, the Borsuk – Ulam theorem, named after Stanisław Ulam and Karol Borsuk, states that every continuous function from an n-sphere into Euclidean n-space maps some pair of antipodal points to the same point.
The no-hair theorem states that, once it achieves a stable condition after formation, a black hole has only three independent physical properties: mass, charge, and angular momentum.
For positive values of a and b, the binomial theorem with n = 2 is the geometrically evident fact that a square of side can be cut into a square of side a, a square of side b, and two rectangles with sides a and b. With n = 3, the theorem states that a cube of side can be cut into a cube of side a, a cube of side b, three a × a × b rectangular boxes, and three a × b × b rectangular boxes.
The Cook – Levin theorem states that the Boolean satisfiability problem is NP-complete, and in fact, this was the first decision problem proved to be NP-complete.
Schaefer's dichotomy theorem states that, for any restriction to Boolean operators that can be used to form these subformulae, the corresponding satisfiability problem is in P or NP-complete.
Goldstone's theorem in quantum field theory states that in a system with broken continuous symmetry, there may exist excitations with arbitrarily low energy, called the Goldstone bosons.
In his 1799 doctorate in absentia, A new proof of the theorem that every integral rational algebraic function of one variable can be resolved into real factors of the first or second degree, Gauss proved the fundamental theorem of algebra which states that every non-constant single-variable polynomial with complex coefficients has at least one complex root.
Moreover, the Banach fixed point theorem states that every contraction mapping on a nonempty complete metric space has a unique fixed point, and that for any x in M the iterated function sequence x, f ( x ), f ( f ( x )), f ( f ( f ( x ))), ... converges to the fixed point.
Fermat's little theorem states that all prime numbers have the above property.
This is a generalization of the Heine – Borel theorem, which states that any closed and bounded subspace S of R < sup > n </ sup > is compact and therefore complete.
The Banach fixed point theorem states that a contraction mapping on a complete metric space admits a fixed point.
The fundamental theorem of calculus states that antidifferentiation is the same as integration.
The Nyquist – Shannon sampling theorem states that a signal can be exactly reconstructed from its samples if the sampling frequency is greater than twice the highest frequency of the signal ; but requires an infinite number of samples.
If X < sub > k </ sub > and Y < sub > k </ sub > are the DFTs of x < sub > n </ sub > and y < sub > n </ sub > respectively then the Plancherel theorem states:

theorem and if
Antiderivatives are important because they can be used to compute definite integrals, using the fundamental theorem of calculus: if F is an antiderivative of the integrable function f, then:
Using the above theorem it is easy to see that the original Borsuk Ulam statement is correct since if we take a map f: S < sup > n </ sup > → ℝ < sup > n </ sup > that does not equalize on any antipodes then we can construct a map g: S < sup > n </ sup > → S < sup > n-1 </ sup > by the formula
The Bolzano – Weierstrass theorem gives an equivalent condition for sequential compactness when considering subsets of Euclidean space: a set then is compact if and only if it is closed and bounded.
If the ideals A and B of R are coprime, then AB = A ∩ B ; furthermore, if C is a third ideal such that A contains BC, then A contains C. The Chinese remainder theorem is an important statement about coprime ideals.
This is because if a group has sectional 2-rank at least 5 then MacWilliams showed that its Sylow 2-subgroups are connected, and the balance theorem implies that any simple group with connected Sylow 2-subgroups is either of component type or characteristic 2 type.
Then Goursat's theorem asserts that ƒ is analytic in an open complex domain Ω if and only if it satisfies the Cauchy – Riemann equation in the domain.
Image: pons_asinorum. png | The bridge of asses theorem states that if A = B then C = D.
Image: Thales ' Theorem Simple. svg | Thales ' theorem: if AC is a diameter, then the angle at B is a right angle.
Thales ' theorem, named after Thales of Miletus states that if A, B, and C are points on a circle where the line AC is a diameter of the circle, then the angle ABC is a right angle.
If the conjecture were true, it would be a generalization of Fermat's last theorem, which could be seen as the special case n = 2: if, then.
By the completeness theorem of first-order logic, a statement is universally valid if and only if it can be deduced from the axioms, so the can also be viewed as asking for an algorithm to decide whether a given statement is provable from the axioms using the rules of logic.
Heawood noticed Kempe's mistake and also observed that if one was satisfied with proving only five colors are needed, one could run through the above argument ( changing only that the minimal counterexample requires 6 colors ) and use Kempe chains in the degree 5 situation to prove the five color theorem.
To prove this, one can combine a proof of the theorem for finite planar graphs with the De Bruijn – Erdős theorem stating that, if every finite subgraph of an infinite graph is k-colorable, then the whole graph is also k-colorable.
A deductive system is called complete if every logically valid formula is the conclusion of some formal deduction, and the completeness theorem for a particular deductive system is the theorem that it is complete in this sense.
The completeness theorem says that if a formula is logically valid then there is a finite deduction ( a formal proof ) of the formula.
Together with soundness ( whose verification is easy ), this theorem implies that a formula is logically valid if and only if it is the conclusion of a formal deduction.
It is deduced from the model existence theorem as follows: if there is no formal proof of a formula then adding its negation to the axioms gives a consisten theory, which has thus a model, so that the formula is not a semantic consequence of the initial theory.
The compactness theorem says that if a formula φ is a logical consequence of a ( possibly infinite ) set of formulas Γ then it is a logical consequence of a finite subset of Γ.

1.858 seconds.