Help


[permalink] [id link]
+
Page "Universal algebra" ¶ 51
from Wikipedia
Edit
Promote Demote Fragment Fix

Some Related Sentences

Tarski's and at
Tarski's § 53 Definitions whose definiendum contains the identity sign discusses how mistakes are made ( at least with respect to zero ).
The T-schema or truth schema ( not to be confused with ' Convention T ') is used to give an inductive definition of truth which lies at the heart of any realisation of Alfred Tarski's semantic theory of truth.

Tarski's and which
* Tarski's axioms: Alfred Tarski ( 1902 – 1983 ) and his students defined elementary Euclidean geometry as the geometry that can be expressed in first-order logic and does not depend on set theory for its logical basis, in contrast to Hilbert's axioms, which involve point sets.
A variant of redundancy theory is the disquotational theory which uses a modified form of Tarski's schema: To say that '" P " is true ' is to say that P. A version of this theory was defended by C. J. F. Williams in his book What is Truth ?.
* The 1997 Rolf Schock Prize in logic and philosophy from the Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences for his conceptually oriented logical works, especially the creation of domain theory, which has made it possible to extend Tarski's semantical paradigm to programming languages as well as to construct models of Curry's combinatory logic and Church's calculus of lambda conversion ; and
Tarski's undefinability theorem: There is no L-formula True ( n ) which defines T *.
Tarski's undefinability theorem ( general form ): Let ( L, N ) be any interpreted formal language which includes negation and has a Gödel numbering g ( x ) such that for every L-formula A ( x ) there is a formula B such that B ↔ A ( g ( B )) holds.
But Tarski's approach was extended by Davidson into an approach to theories of meaning for natural languages, which involves treating " truth " as a primitive, rather than a defined concept.
This is similar to Tarski's free group problem, which asks whether two different non-abelian finitely generated free groups have the same elementary theory.
A logic for which Tarski's method is applicable, is called algebraizable.
His first work was a commentary on Alfred Tarski's theory of truth, which he has worked on since 1972.
In fact they only needed the real version of the conjecture, defined below, to prove this result, which would be a positive solution to Tarski's exponential function problem.
A variant of redundancy theory is the disquotational theory, which uses a modified form of Tarski's schema: To say that "' P ' is true " is to say that P. Yet another version of deflationism is the prosentential theory of truth, first developed by Dorothy Grover, Joseph Camp, and Nuel Belnap as an elaboration of Ramsey's claims.

Tarski's and model-theoretic
* Tarski's definition of model-theoretic satisfaction, now called the T-schema
Ultimately, the reason for this weakening is that whereas the model-theoretic satisfaction relation can be defined, truth itself cannot, due to Tarski's theorem.

Tarski's and developed
However, the methods developed by Frege and Tarski for the study of mathematical language have been extended greatly by Tarski's student Richard Montague and other linguists working in formal semantics to show that the distinction between mathematical language and natural language may not be as great as it seems.
* Relation algebra, invented by DeMorgan, and developed by Charles Sanders Peirce, Ernst Schröder, Tarski, and Tarski's students.

Tarski's and by
This result, known as Tarski's undefinability theorem, was discovered independently by Gödel ( when he was working on the proof of the incompleteness theorem ) and by Alfred Tarski.
The analysis of logical concepts and the machinery of formalization that is essential to Principia Mathematica ( 3 vols., 1910 – 1913 ) ( by Bertrand Russell, 1872 – 1970, and Alfred North Whitehead, 1861 – 1947 ), to Russell's theory of descriptions, to Kurt Gödel's ( 1906 – 1978 ) incompleteness theorems, and to Alfred Tarski's ( 1901 – 1983 ) theory of truth, is ultimately due to Frege.
This result, known as Tarski's undefinability theorem, was discovered independently by Gödel ( when he was working on the proof of the incompleteness theorem ) and by Alfred Tarski.
Tarski's circle-squaring problem is the challenge, posed by Alfred Tarski in 1925, to take a disc in the plane, cut it into finitely many pieces, and reassemble the pieces so as to get a square of equal area.
Unlike the generalized solution to Tarski's circle-squaring problem, the axiom of choice is not required for the proof, and the decomposition and reassembly can actually be carried out " physically "; the pieces can, in theory, be cut with scissors from paper and reassembled by hand.
There is a subtlety about this definition: by Tarski's undefinability theorem it is not in general possible to define the truth of a formula of set theory in the language of set theory.
In mathematics, the Tarski's theorem, proved by Alfred Tarski, states that in ZF the theorem " For every infinite set A, there is a bijective map between the sets A and A × A " implies the axiom of choice.
The sentences whose existence is secured by the diagonal lemma can then, in turn, be used to prove fundamental limitative results such as Gödel's incompleteness theorems and Tarski's indefinability theorem.
Tarski's undefinability theorem, stated and proved by Alfred Tarski in 1936, is an important limitative result in mathematical logic, the foundations of mathematics, and in formal semantics.
A semantic proof of Tarski's theorem from Post's theorem is obtained by reductio ad absurdum as follows.
The proof of Tarski's undefinability theorem in this form is again by reductio ad absurdum.
Smullyan ( 1991, 2001 ) has argued forcefully that Tarski's undefinability theorem deserves much of the attention garnered by Gödel's incompleteness theorems.
Tarski's basic goal was to provide a rigorously logical definition of the expression " true sentence " within a specific formal language and to clarify the fundamental conditions of material adequacy that would have to be met by any definition of the truth-predicate.
Soon after Alfred Tarski joined Berkeley's mathematics department in 1942, Robinson began to do major work on the foundations of mathematics, building on Tarski's concept of " essential undecidability ," by proving a number of mathematical theories undecidable.
Quine suggested an unnatural linguistic resolution to such logical antinomies, inspired by Bertrand Russell's Type theory and Tarski's work.
The study of the algebraization process ( and notion ) as topic of interest by itself, not necessarily by Tarski's method, has led to the development of abstract algebraic logic.

Tarski's and Tarski
It was Tarski who stated the result in its most general form, and so the theorem is often known as Tarski's fixed point theorem.
* Tarski's undefinability theorem ( Gödel and Tarski in the 1930s )
We will first state a simplified version of Tarski's theorem, then state and prove in the next section the theorem Tarski actually proved in 1936.
This result is often attributed to Alfred Tarski, but Tarski's fixed point theorem pertains to monotone functions on complete lattices.
Tarski's axioms, due to Alfred Tarski, are an axiom set for the substantial fragment of Euclidean geometry, called " elementary ," that is formulable in first-order logic with identity, and requiring no set theory.
Tarski's axiomatization is shorter than its rivals, in a sense Tarski and Givant ( 1999 ) make explicit.

Tarski's and well
* Formal theories of truth such as used in formal logic and mathematics, as well as Alfred Tarski's semantic theory of truth and Saul Kripke's theories of truth.
Gödel also discovered the undefinability theorem in 1930, while proving his incompleteness theorems published in 1931, and well before the 1936 publication of Tarski's work ( Murawski 1998 ).

0.195 seconds.