Help


[permalink] [id link]
+
Page "Philosophical Investigations" ¶ 22
from Wikipedia
Edit
Promote Demote Fragment Fix

Some Related Sentences

Wittgenstein and rejects
Wittgenstein rejects a variety of ways of thinking about what the meaning of a word is, or how meanings can be identified.
McDowell argues that Wittgenstein does present the paradox ( as Kripke argues ), but he argues further that Wittgenstein rejects the paradox on the grounds that it assimilates understanding and interpretation.

Wittgenstein and idea
In the years between the two works Wittgenstein came to reject the idea that underpinned logical atomism, that there were ultimate " simples " from which a language should, or even could, be constructed.
The philosophical significance of such a method for Wittgenstein was that it alleviated a confusion, namely the idea that logical inferences are justified by rules.
Nevertheless, Wittgenstein managed to sell this idea, and it was enthusiastically adopted as an unquestionable revelation.
Wittgenstein rejected the idea that language has a direct connection to reality and argued that concepts do not need to be so clearly defined to be meaningful.

Wittgenstein and ostensive
The process of ostensive definition itself was critically appraised by Ludwig Wittgenstein.
Wittgenstein argues for this making a series of moves to show that to understand an ostensive definition presupposes an understanding of the way the word being defined is used.
Ludwig Wittgenstein writes: So one might say: the ostensive definition explains the use — the meaningof the word when the overall role of the word in language is clear.
The limitations of ostensive definition are exploited in a famous argument from the Philosophical Investigations ( which deal primarily with the philosophy of language ), the private language argument, in which Wittgenstein asks if it is possible to have a private language that no one else can understand.

Wittgenstein and definitions
Wittgenstein argues that definitions emerge from what he termed " forms of life ", roughly the culture and society in which they are used.

Wittgenstein and can
For Wittgenstein, there is no single, coherent " sample " or " object " that we can call " meaning ".
Thus, Wittgenstein argues, if we can talk about something, then it is not private, in the sense considered.
For Wittgenstein, thought is inevitably tied to language, which is inherently social ; therefore, there is no ' inner ' space in which thoughts can occur.
Wittgenstein has also said that " language is inherent and transcendental ", which is also not difficult to understand, since we can only comprehend and explain transcendental affairs through language.
In addition to ambiguous sentences, Wittgenstein discussed figures which can be seen and understood in two different ways.
An example Wittgenstein uses is the " duckrabbit ", a picture that can be seen as either a duck or a rabbit.
To show this, Wittgenstein provided examples of sentences or expressions that can be interpreted in more than one way.
Richard Rorty, Kierkegaard, and Wittgenstein challenge the sense of questioning whether our particular concepts are related to the world in an appropriate way, whether we can justify our ways of describing the world as compared with other ways.
Wittgenstein shows that this operator can cope with the whole of predicate logic with identity, defining the quantifiers at 5. 52, and showing how identity would then be handled at 5. 53-5. 532.
Whereas Russell believed the names ( like x ) in his theory should refer to things we can know epistemically, Wittgenstein thought they should refer to the " objects " that make up his metaphysics.
By objects, Wittgenstein did not mean physical objects in the world, but the absolute base of logical analysis, that can be combined but not divided ( TLP 2. 02 – 2. 0201 ).
We can communicate such a game of chess in the exact way that Wittgenstein says a proposition represents the world.
* Philosopher John Searle suggests that the Western canon can be roughly defined as " a certain Western intellectual tradition that goes from, say, Socrates to Wittgenstein in philosophy, and from Homer to James Joyce in literature ..."
Ludwig Wittgenstein made a remark recorded by Friedrich Waismann: " To be sure, I can imagine what Heidegger means by being and anxiety " which has been construed by some commentators as sympathetic to Heidegger's philosophical approach.
Wittgenstein also mentions the will, life after death, and God ; arguing that " When the answer cannot be put into words, neither can the question be put into words ".
Wittgenstein wrote to Siegfried Rapp on June 5, 1950: You don't build a house just so that someone else can live in it.
In contrast to this approach, Wittgenstein observed, following Moore's paradox, that one can say " He believes it, but it isn't so ", but not " He knows it, but it isn't so ".
However, this critique of metaphysics, carried on by the first Wittgenstein, in his 1921 Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus, for example, has been in return criticized by philosophers, such as Heidegger in his 1927 Being and Time, as a form of positivism or, worse, scientism, which is accused of having decided to abandon the most important questions about humanity and the Being, under the pretext that no definitive answer can be brought to them.
Wittgenstein famously said, " whatever can be said, can be said clearly "; but does this apply to economics?
While Upaya or the Noble Lie can be ( as in Wittgenstein ) teaching devices or stratagems to be superseded at a later stage, in many cases the laity only ever learns the exoteric doctrine, with only the elite ever learning the true esoteric version.
In PI 201a Wittgenstein explicitly states the rule-following paradox: " This was our paradox: no course of action could be determined by a rule, because any course of action can be made out to accord with the rule ".
In this latter view, endorsed by Wittgenstein in Wright's readings, there are no facts about numerical addition that man has so far not discovered, so when we come upon such situations, we can flesh out our interpretations further.

Wittgenstein and provide
The main contention of such readings is that Wittgenstein in the Tractatus does not provide a theoretical account of language that relegates ethics and philosophy to a mystical realm of the unsayable.

Wittgenstein and us
He implores his reader: “ don ’ t think, but look !” ( PI § 66 ) Philosophy, to Wittgenstein, “ simply puts everything before us, and neither explains nor deduces anything.

Wittgenstein and with
Logical empiricism ( aka logical positivism or neopositivism ) was an early 20th century attempt to synthesize the essential ideas of British empiricism ( e. g. a strong emphasis on sensory experience as the basis for knowledge ) with certain insights from mathematical logic that had been developed by Gottlob Frege and Ludwig Wittgenstein.
In his later years, Hayek recalled a discussion of philosophy with Wittgenstein, when both were officers during World War I.
He was, with Bertrand Russell, Ludwig Wittgenstein, and ( before them ) Gottlob Frege, one of the founders of the analytic tradition in philosophy.
Writing decades after Cantor's death, Wittgenstein lamented that mathematics is " ridden through and through with the pernicious idioms of set theory ," which he dismissed as " utter nonsense " that is " laughable " and " wrong ".
In the philosophy of language these views are often associated with Wittgenstein ’ s later works and with ordinary language philosophers such as Paul Grice, John Searle and J. L. Austin.
The early Wittgenstein was concerned with the logical relationship between propositions and the world, and believed that by providing an account of the logic underlying this relationship he had solved all philosophical problems.
According to a family tree prepared in Jerusalem after World War II, Wittgenstein's paternal great-grandfather was Moses Meier, a Jewish land agent who lived with his wife, Brendel Simon, in Bad Laasphe in the Principality of Wittgenstein, Westphalia.
Karl Wittgenstein ( 1847 – 1913 ) became an industrial tycoon, and by the late 1880s was one of the richest men in Europe, with an effective monopoly on Austria's steel cartel.
And besides Post and Wittgenstein, others credited with the tabular structure include Łukasiewicz, Schröder, Alfred North Whitehead, William Stanley Jevons, John Venn, and Clarence Irving Lewis.
Compare, for example, Proposition 4. 024 of the Tractatus, where Wittgenstein asserts that we understand a proposition when we know what happens if it is true, with Schlick's assertion that " To state the circumstances under which a proposition is true is the same as stating its meaning.
Analytic philosophy of religion has also been preoccupied with Ludwig Wittgenstein, as well as his interpretation of Søren Kierkegaard's philosophy of religion.
Wittgenstein begins the book with a quotation from St. Augustine, whom he cites as a proponent of the generalized and limited conception that he then summarizes:
" Or Wittgenstein may indicate such a response by beginning with a long dash, as he does before the question above: — But what is the meaning of the word ' five '?
" However, In proposing the thought experiment involving the fictional character, Robinson Crusoe, a captain shipwrecked on a desolate island with no other inhabitant, Wittgenstein shows that language is not in all cases a social phenomenon ( although, they are for most case ); instead the criterion for a language is grounded in a set of interrelated normative activities: teaching, explanations, techniques and criteria of correctness.
The discussion of private languages was revitalized in 1982 with the publication of Saul Kripke's book Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language.
Kripke's version of Wittgenstein, although philosophically interesting, has been facetiously called Kripkenstein, with some scholars such as Gordon Baker and Peter Hacker, Colin McGinn, and John McDowell, seeing it as a radical misinterpretation of Wittgenstein's text.
Norman Malcolm credits Piero Sraffa with providing Wittgenstein with the conceptual break that founded the Philosophical Investigations, by means of a rude gesture on Sraffa's part:
" Wittgenstein was insisting that a proposition and that which it describes must have the same ' logical form ', the same ' logical multiplicity ', Sraffa made a gesture, familiar to Neapolitans as meaning something like disgust or contempt, of brushing the underneath of his chin with an outward sweep of the finger-tips of one hand.
In 1991, Singer was due to speak along with R. M. Hare and Georg Meggle at the fifteenth International Wittgenstein Symposium in Kirchberg, Austria.
Wittgenstein is to be credited with the invention or at least the popularization of truth tables ( 4. 31 ) and truth conditions ( 4. 431 ) which now constitute the standard semantic analysis of first-order sentential logic.

0.439 seconds.