Help


[permalink] [id link]
+
Page "J. Baird Callicott" ¶ 12
from Wikipedia
Edit
Promote Demote Fragment Fix

Some Related Sentences

Callicott and has
J. Baird Callicott is an American philosopher whose work has been at the forefront of the new field of environmental philosophy and ethics.
Callicott has explored the possibility of a Judeo-Christian citizenship environmental ethic as a more radical alternative to the familiar Judeo-Christian stewardship environmental ethic that was developed in response to criticism from environmental historians and philosophers.
In response to Callicott ’ s elaboration of the Aldo Leopold land ethic, the land ethic ( and, by implication, Callicott ’ s own non-anthropocentric, holistic environmental ethic to the extent that it may differ from Leopold ’ s ) has been subject to the charge of ecofascism ,” notably leveled by Tom Regan.
Additionally, Callicott has been criticized for espousing an overbearing and impolitic monism in environmental ethics.

Callicott and with
Callicott supports a holistic, non-anthropocentric environmental ethic which is in accordance with Leopold's view that " A thing is right when it tends to preserve the integrity, stability, and beauty of the biotic community.
Callicott ’ s book In Defense of the Land Ethic ( 1989 ) explores the intellectual foundations of Leopold's outlook and seeks to provide it with a more complete philosophical treatment ; and a following publication titled Beyond the Land Ethic ( 1999 ) further extends Leopold ’ s environmental philosophy.
Callicott is co-Editor-in-Chief with Robert Frodeman of the award-winning, two-volume A-Z Encyclopedia of Environmental Ethics and Philosophy, published by Macmillan in 2009.
As an expatriate Southerner, fresh from the pitched battles of the Civil Rights struggle in Memphis, Tennessee ,” Callicott believed that the environment was under wholesale assault from every direction with no surcease in sight and that Civil Rights was a cause already won in the republic of ideas and in the courts ( if not on Main Street in Memphis ).” He was a concerned citizen, but was also, more particularly, a challenged philosopher .” So Callicott asked how, as a philosopher, could contribute to a rethinking of human nature and a reconstruction of human values to help bring them into line with the relatively new ideas about the nature of the environment emerging from ecology and the new physics .”
When the details of that worldview are shown to be inconsistent with themselves or unable to account for all the facts, the theory is revised accordingly ; the evolutionary-ecological worldview is thus self-correcting and is therefore, Callicott believes, becoming ever more refined.
Callicott counters that his quarrel is with an idea, not the places trammeled by the idea, the preservation of which places he appears to be as ardently supportive as any other environmentalist.
This idea indicates by its very name what the primary goal of wildland preservation is, whereas the wilderness idea is historically associated with outdoor recreation and thus, Callicott claims, confuses the preservation issue and fosters incoherent and contradictory wildlands-use policies.

Callicott and conservation
Callicott instead proposes that, because wilderness areas serve purposes of biological conservation, they should be reconceived more fittingly as biodiversity reserves .”

Callicott and philosophy
Callicott was instrumental in developing the field of environmental philosophy and in 1971 taught the world's first course in environmental ethics.
Aldo Leopold's A Sand County Almanac is one of environmental philosophy ’ s seminal texts, and Callicott is widely considered to be the leading contemporary exponent of Leopold's land ethic.
Callicott ’ s Earth ’ s Insights ( 1994 ) is also considered an important contribution to the budding field of comparative environmental philosophy ; a special edition of the journal Worldviews: Environment, Culture, Religion ( Vol.
In 1969, Callicott joined the philosophy department of Wisconsin State University-Stevens Point ( now the University of Wisconsin-Stevens Point ).
Callicott writes that the landscape that had helped shape and inspire the nascent evolutionary-ecological thought of the youthful Muir and that of the mature Leopold was the perfect setting for ( me ) to inaugurate ( my ) life-long vocation as a founder of academic environmental philosophy .” In 1995, he joined the Department of Philosophy and Religion Studies at the University of North Texas in Denton.
The tradition of dichotomous thinking in Western philosophy inclines most philosophers to dismiss Hume ’ s ethics as a kind of irrational emotivism, despite the fact that, Callicott believes, Hume clearly provides a key role for reason in moral action and judgment.
Callicott ’ s comparative environmental philosophy also involves a tightrope walk between pluralism and monism.

Callicott and ethics
Callicott held the position of Professor of Philosophy and Natural Resources at the University of Wisconsin – Stevens Point from 1969 to 1995, where he taught the world ’ s first course in environmental ethics in 1971.
Callicott traces the conceptual foundations of the Leopold land ethic first back to Charles Darwin ’ s analysis of the moral sense in the Descent of Man and ultimately to David Hume ’ s grounding of ethics in the moral sentiments espoused in An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Morals.
The distinctiveness of environmental ethics turns on the question of non-anthropocentrism, and that question turns on the question of nature ’ s intrinsic value, according to Callicott.
In The Conceptual Foundations of the Land Ethic ,” Callicott replies that Leopold presented the land ethic as an accretion to our evolving complex set of ethics.
The general theory that Callicott espouses, Humean communitarianism, correlates ethics to community membership.
* J. Baird Callicott ( Philosophy Department, 1965 – 94 ) – founder of academic environmental ethics discipline ; now at the University of North Texas

Callicott and based
As Andrew Light observes, Callicott does not insist that the Leopold land ethic is based on the uniquely true worldview of evolutionary biology and ecology.
Callicott ’ s justification for this claim is an analysis based on the following criteria for tenability: self-consistency ; comprehensiveness ; self-correction ; universality ; and beauty.

Callicott and on
Callicott was born in Memphis, Tennessee on May 9, 1941, to distinguished regional artist and art instructor Burton H. Callicott ( 1907 – 2003 ), of the Memphis Academy of Arts ( now Memphis College of Arts ).
For 26 years, Callicott lived and taught in the northern reaches of Wisconsin's sand counties, located on the Wisconsin River, just ninety miles from Aldo Leopold's storied shack and John Muir's first homestead on Fountain Lake, the region that stirred the souls of two very influential environmental thinkers.
Callicott offers a subjectivist theory of nature ’ s intrinsic value: he does not challenge the modern classical distinction between subject and object, but rather insists that all value originates in subjects ( human or otherwise ) and is conferred by those subjects on various objects.
Worldviews: Environment, Culture, Religion ( Special Theme Issue on J. Baird Callicott ’ s Earth ’ s Insights ).

Callicott and recent
Most recent criticisms have been leveled at Callicott ’ s works addressing the idea of wilderness, the sanctum sanctorum of the twentieth-century environmental movement.

Callicott and paradigm
Callicott believes that an adequate environmental ethic — an environmental-ethics paradigm that addresses actual environmental concerns — must be holistic.

Callicott and from
In 1959, Callicott graduated from Memphis's then racially segregated Messick High School and attended Southwestern at Memphis ( now Rhodes College ), earning a B.

Callicott and
This reply led to another criticism: that Callicott provides no second-order principles to prioritize duties to fellow humans and those to the biotic community when they conflict.
Callicott, John Baird Page 124 in W. P. Cunningham et al., ed.

Callicott and .”
In response, Callicott offered two second-order principles as a framework to adjudicate between conflicting first-order duties: 1 ) obligations generated by membership in more venerable and intimate communities take precedence over those generated in more recently emerged and impersonal communities ”; 2 ) stronger interests take precedence over duties generated by weaker interests .” Because our various human community memberships are both more venerable and intimate and because human interests in enjoying rights to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness are very strong, Callicott argues that our traditional obligations to individual fellow human beings trump our obligations to preserve the integrity, stability, and beauty of the biotic community — at least, he believes, when it comes to the prospect of culling members of the overpopulous Homo sapiens species.

Callicott and wilderness
Some scholars acknowledge the intellectual merits of Callicott ’ s critique of the wilderness idea, but regard it as both a betrayal of one of Aldo Leopold ’ s most cherished causes and as giving aid and comfort to the environmental movement ’ s enemies.

Callicott and by
In addition, his arrangement for " Cottonfield Blues " was performed by early Delta blues musicians Garfield Akers and Mississippi Joe Callicott in 1929.

Callicott and is
Callicott is, perhaps, best known for his research which explores an Aldo Leopold ethic as a response to global climate change.
It is wrong when it tends otherwise " — Callicott espouses a holistic, non-anthropocentric environmental ethic.
In sum, Callicott is a theoretical monist and an interpersonal and normative pluralist.

0.346 seconds.